Dana lives in a country that follows right-wing totalitarianism. therefore, it is most likely that:

This is a preview. Log in to get access

Abstract

What is the impact of dictatorships on postdictatorial civil societies? Bottom-up theories suggest that totalitarian dictatorships destroy civil society while authoritarian ones allow for its development. Top-down theories of civil society suggest that totalitarianism can create civil societies while authoritarianism is unlikely to. This article argues that both these perspectives suffer from a one-dimensional understanding of civil society that conflates strength and autonomy. Accordingly we distinguish these two dimensions and argue that totalitarian dictatorships tend to create organizationally strong but heteronomous civil societies, while authoritarian ones tend to create relatively autonomous but organizationally weak civil societies. We then test this conceptualization by closely examining the historical connection between dictatorship and civil society development in Italy (a posttotalitarian case) and Spain (a postauthoritarian one). Our article concludes by reflecting on the implications of our argument for democratic theory, civil society theory, and theories of regime variation.

Journal Information

Current issues are now on the Chicago Journals website. Read the latest issue.Established in 1895 as the first US scholarly journal in its field, the American Journal of Sociology (AJS) presents pathbreaking work from all areas of sociology, with an emphasis on theory building and innovative methods. AJS strives to speak to the general sociology reader and is open to contributions from across the social sciences—political science, economics, history, anthropology, and statistics in addition to sociology—that seriously engage the sociological literature to forge new ways of understanding the social. AJS offers a substantial book review section that identifies the most salient work of both emerging and enduring scholars of social science. Commissioned review essays appear occasionally, offering the readers a comparative, in-depth examination of prominent titles.

Publisher Information

Since its origins in 1890 as one of the three main divisions of the University of Chicago, The University of Chicago Press has embraced as its mission the obligation to disseminate scholarship of the highest standard and to publish serious works that promote education, foster public understanding, and enrich cultural life. Today, the Journals Division publishes more than 70 journals and hardcover serials, in a wide range of academic disciplines, including the social sciences, the humanities, education, the biological and medical sciences, and the physical sciences.

Rights & Usage

This item is part of a JSTOR Collection.
For terms and use, please refer to our Terms and Conditions
© 2015 by The University of Chicago. All rights reserved.
Request Permissions

Abstract

The notion of totalitarianism as a singular event in the twentieth century, beginning with his philosophical and political analysis of contradictions and ways of transformation into the contemporary era of the end of the sovereignty of the nation-state. The most significant political theorists of the twentieth century, such as Hannah Arendt, Franz Neumann, and Carl J. Friedrich, start from the uncanny event of the absolute novelty concerning the phenomenon of total rule in modern times. But it could be a real problem. If totalitarianism transgresses the traditional notions of political philosophy, such as were forms of governments blended in antiquity, the Middle Ages, and the New era—tyranny, dictatorship, despotism, sovereign monarchy—then it might be obvious that the term defines as negative (a) as well as the possibility of non-democratic political order and (b) as the completion of the epochal-historical form in which a modern set of economics, politics, and culture appears.

Keywords

  • Political philosophy
  • Singular event
  • Global order
  • Total state
  • A society of control
  • The end of sovereignty
  • Corporatism

Notes

  1. 1.

    The terms totalitarianism, total state, and total governance are primarily related to national socialism as the ideology and Nazi politics of Germany since the 1920s as a movement to the end and the defeat in the Second World War in 1945. Italian fascism is referred to as the corporate state, which does not mean that the totality of the rule does not accompany this movement with the same principles of one leader and ideologies. But the difference is that the Nazis from the very beginning have a radical idea of geopolitical conquest of Europe and the world, whereby Italy in this regard relies on the mythical projection of the Roman Empire. In the use of the concepts of totalitarianism, the total governance, and the total state, the case of Stalinism as a paradigmatic way of constructing socialism based on the ideology of Lenin and Stalin shows that it is the same thing. So, the total state cannot be based on terror over racial-national minorities, but on the terror against the bourgeois class and the “enemy” of the new social order. The problem with terminological use refers to the real problem of equivalence and the difference between the three types of totalitarian rule in the twentieth century. It will be not unusual, however, to consider that communism and socialist types of totalitarianism were sufficiently condemned in the twentieth century from 1945 to 1989 in the world. The Black Book of Communism: Crimes, Terror, Repression seeks to show in the name of the symmetry of crimes committed in totalitarian systems of real Socialism that crimes of communism were greater than fascism, because the totalitarian rule in the USSR, China, Yugoslavia, the People’s Republic of Korea, and the whole of Eastern Europe has secured victory over fascism in the Second World War. As a key argument, it continues to take the view of historian Ernst Nolte that fascism has been a reaction to communism established in Russia in 1917 (Nolte 2008 and Evans 1991).

  2. 2.

    The emergence of total rule in the twentieth century in modern Europe is undoubtedly an ambivalent process. On the one hand, it is about accounting with liberalism in economics and politics, indicating that the totalitarian order in its effectiveness is the most radical change in the history of modernity from the French Revolution until the end of the First World War. On the other hand, the strange, total rule would be impossible without a corporate system of economics. Its fundamental task of generating benefits in the traditional notion of the market and surplus value is socialized by making the formal condition a subject of political control of the economy (Germany and Italy), or as in Stalinism, the collapse of civil society and the capitalist economy becomes the means of establishing a total rule of command policy in form permanent terror over the subject of the “revolution”—the proletarian class and the peasantry. In researching the genealogy of total rule in the works of Theodor W. Adorno and Hannah Arendt regarding the pathology of modern in imperialist demonstrations of European states and the destruction of public freedom, Danna Villa derives from the underlying assumption of the “postmodern turn” in understanding the political origin of Hannah Arendt: that, in other words, totalitarianism was not a necessity, but only one of the possibilities of the historical development of European modern politics (Villa 2008, 212).

References

  • Agamben, Giorgio. 2002. Homo sacer: Die souveräne Macht und das, Nackte Leben. Frankfurt/M: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. State of Exception. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2010. Herrschaft und Herrlichkeit: Zur theologischen Genealogie von Ökonomie und Regiereung (Homo Sacer II.2). Berlin: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hannah. 1972. Civil Disobedience in Crises of the Republic, 49–102. New York: Harcourt Brace & Comp.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1973. The Origins of Totalitarianism. New York: Harvest & Brace Jovanovich.

    Google Scholar 

  • Badiou, Alain. 1998. Abrégé de métapolitique. Paris: Seuil.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bauman, Zygmunt. 1989. Modernity and the Holocaust. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benjamin, Walter. 1996. Das Kunstwerk im Zeitalter Seiner Technischen Reproduzierbarkeit: Drei Studien der Kunstsoziologie. 22nd ed. Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Canovan, Margaret. 2006. Arendt’s Theory of Totalitarianism: A Reassessment. In The Cambridge Companion to Hannah Arendt, ed. Dana Villa, 25–43. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deleuze, Gilles. 1992. Postscript to the Societies of Control. October 59 (Winter): 3–7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, Jacques. 2002. The University Without Condition. In Without Alibi. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    CrossRef  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. Rogues: Two Essays on Reason. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eco, Umberto. 1995. Ur-Fascism. The New York Review of Books. June 22. http://www.nybooks.com/articles/1856

  • Evans, J. Richard. 1991. Im Schatten Hitlers? History and Vergangengheitsbewältigung in der Bundesrepublik. Frankfurt/M: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, Michel. 2003. What Is Enlightenment? In The Essential Works of Michel Foucault: Ethics, Vol. I. New York: New Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedrich, Carl J., and Zbignew Brzezinski. 1956. Totalitarian Dictatorship and Autocracy. 2nd ed. New York, Washington, London: Frederick A. Praeger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldhagen, Daniel. 1997. Hitler’s Willing Executioners: Ordinary Germans and the Holocaust. New York: Vintage.

    CrossRef  Google Scholar 

  • Groys, Boris. 2008. Gesamtkunstwerk Stalin. Munich: Hanser.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grunberger, Richard. 2005. A Social History of the Third Reich. London: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 2004. Zu Ernst Jünger. GA, Vol. 90. Frankfurt a. M: V. Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, Edmund. 2007. Die Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaften und die transzendentale Phänomenologie: Eine Einleitung in die phänomenologische Philosophie. 3rd ed. Hamburg: F. Meiner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Intelmann, Peter. 2009. Franz Neumann: Weimar, Nationalsozialismus—und was dann? In Kritische Theorie des Staates: Staat und Recht bei Franz L. Neumann, ed. Samuel Salzborn, 57–75. Nomos: Baden-Baden.

    CrossRef  Google Scholar 

  • Jaspers, Karl. 1966. Wohin treibt die Bundesrepublik? Tatsachen—Gefahren—Chancen. München: R. Pipper & Co. Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kracauer, Siegfried. 2004. From Caligari to Hitler: A Psychological History of German Film. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinas, Emmanuel. 2003. The Other, Utopia, and Justice. In Entre Nous, ed. Emmanuel Levinas. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lietzmann, J. Hans. 1999. Politikwissenschaft im ‘Zeitalter der Diktaturen’. The Die Entwicklung der Totalitarismustheorie Carl Joachim Friedrichs. Opladen: Leske + Budrich.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maier, Hans, ed. 2003. Totalitarismus und Politische Religionen: Vol. I. Paderborn: F. Schöningh.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marcuse, Herbert. 1980. Der Kampf gegen den Liberalismus in der totalitäre Staatsauffasung. In Kultur und Gesellschaft: Vol. I, 13th ed., 17–55. Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1985. Soviet Marxism. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mouffe, Chantal. 2005. The Return of the Political. London and New York: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neumann, Franz. 2009. Behemoth: The Structure and Practice of National Socialism 1933–1944. Chicago: Ivan R. Dee.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nolte, Ernst. 2008. Der Faschismus in Seiner Epoche. Vol. Issue 6. Munich: Piper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paić, Žarko. 2011. Posthuman Condition: The End of Man and Odds of Other History. Zagreb: Litteris.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. Sovereignty as a Nomos of Politics: Rousseau and Schmitt. In Freedom Without Power: The Politics in the Networks of Entropy, 63–99. Zagreb: White Wave.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plessner, Helmuth. 2001. Die verspätete Nation. Frankfurt/M: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rancière, Jacques. 1995. La mesentente: Politique et la Philosophie. Paris: Galilée.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rensmann, Lars. 2009. The Total Staat Als Un-Staat: Hannah Arendts und Franz Neumanns politische Theorien űber totalitäre Herrschaft. In Kritische Theorie des Staates. Staat und Recht bei Franz L. Neumann, ed. Samuel Salzborn, 161–193. Nomos Verlag: Baden-Baden.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosanvallon, Pierre. 2008. Counter-Democracy: Politics and age of Confidence. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    CrossRef  Google Scholar 

  • Schmitt, Carl. 1974. Der Nomos der Erde im Völkerrecht des Jus Publicum Europeeum. 2nd ed. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Villa, Danna. 2008. Public Freedom. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press.

    CrossRef  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

  1. University of Zagreb, Zagreb, Croatia

    Žarko Paić

Authors

  1. Žarko Paić

    You can also search for this author in PubMed Google Scholar

Rights and permissions

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Paić, Ž. (2022). Totalitarianism Without Subject: The End of the Total State and the “Ideology” of the Corporatism. In: The Return of Totalitarianism . Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-18942-5_2

Download citation

  • .RIS
  • .ENW
  • .BIB
  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-18942-5_2

  • Published: 08 December 2022

  • Publisher Name: Palgrave Macmillan, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-031-18941-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-031-18942-5

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

What is the best way to determine what kind of government a country has quizlet?

The constitution mutual explains what kind of government a country has and how that government functions. It also tells us how a country's laws are made, and it explains the rights and responsibilities of citizens. Most modern countries have written constitutions.

Which of the following is most likely a characteristic of developed economies?

Which of the following is most likely a characteristic of developed economies? Such economies often follow a command economy in which all factors of production are strictly state owned and state controlled. Most developed economies are supported by strong, effective, and market-supporting formal institutions.

Which of the following is an example of opportunism?

Examples of opportunism include misleading, cheating, and confusing other parties in transactions that will increase transaction costs.

Which pillar refers to the internalized taken for granted values and beliefs that guide individual and firm behavior?

The cognitive pillar refers to the internalized values and beliefs that guide individual and firm behavior.